Does nature have value beyond what it provides humans?
You can drive a nail with a hammer, and you can pull one. With a
pencil you can write a poem or a song. Hammers and pencils are clearly
useful – instrumentally valuable, that is. But if the pencil snaps or
the hammer cracks, then it’s off to the trash heap.
Your daughter is different. She may be useful in mowing the lawn and
providing a tax write-off, but she also possesses value far beyond her
utility. Daughters are also intrinsically valuable.
What about the intrinsic value of nature? Does nature have only
pencil- and hammer-like values, or does nature also possess intrinsic
value?
A handful of very vocal conservationists these days make assertions about the exclusive importance of nature’s instrumental value. We will not be motivated to protect nature, they assert, unless we appreciate the full range of “ecosystems services”
nature provides to humans (water purification, pollination and the
like). In turn, they make claims about, even ridicule, the failure of
appeals to conservation premised upon the intrinsic value of nature.
This fervent commitment to the instrumental value of nature even
trickles down to individual, highly sentient, parts of nature. It’s okay
to kill lions, they say, because killing a lion for a trophy can
generate important conservation revenue. A lion’s life is, they say, instrumentally valuable, a means to an end.
All of these assertions are built upon the assumed truth of an
empirical claim. They assume that only by appealing to the instrumental
value of nature will we motivate environmental action, because, they
assume, that’s how humans value nature. We are, that is, anthropocentric
(from the Greek, meaning human-centered). Everyone knows that, right?
Actually, as it turns out, not right.
Widely held view
In our research we found that the premise currently underpinning so much conservation effort is wildly mistaken.
A survey we conducted
with Ohio residents – hardly a bastion of
tree-hugging-granola-munching-Birkenstock-wearing-Prius drivers –
demonstrated that more than 82% of Ohioans acknowledged the intrinsic
value of wildlife. A nationally representative survey
of adults revealed very similar numbers (81%). Moreover, we see this
high level of intrinsic value attribution across demographic groups:
whether rural residents or urbanites, rich or poor, male or female,
hunters or non-hunters. Interestingly, more than 90% of people who
strongly identified as “conservationists” in the Ohio survey
acknowledged nature’s intrinsic value. This suggests that
conservationists who reject nature’s intrinsic value are out of the
mainstream of their peers.
But if so very many of us believe in nature’s intrinsic value, then
why do we seem to behave otherwise? Why do we continue to pollute more
than necessary? Why do we continue to destroy natural habitats by
expanding human developments in places where human well-being is already
high? Why do we as a society make so many decisions that appear to be,
or that actually are, inconsistent with the idea that nature possesses
intrinsic value?
Perhaps because while you believe in nature’s intrinsic value, you
don’t believe that enough of the rest of us share your belief for it to
be an effective basis for conservation. Perhaps, that is, we’ve bought
into a false narrative about our own ethical beliefs?
Acknowledgment
This is one of the many mistaken ideas about nature’s intrinsic
value, but it’s an important one. The assumptions we make (rightly or
wrongly) about the world, including about the way people value that
world, control the approaches we take or believe to be viable, the
questions we ask or fail to ask, and ultimately the outcomes we can
expect or never even imagine. It’s vital that we get this right; it
colors every aspect of our relationship with nature.
So, let’s give ourselves some credit, even a little pat on the back
(but gently, only one hand, just for a moment). Now, let’s think hard
about what widespread acknowledgment of nature’s intrinsic value means.
It means that we are not necessarily the equivalent of morally
self-absorbed infants. We are more morally mature than we might have
imagined, than people keep insisting.
But this is bittersweet, because with moral maturity comes moral
responsibility. As we acknowledge that we attribute intrinsic value to
nature, we must hold ourselves accountable for that acknowledgment.
We invite conservationists and the conservation community to engage
in a moment of reflection: we say we believe nature has intrinsic value;
from that belief, what follows?
No comments:
Post a Comment